Options
Ludwig, Bernd
Loading...
Preferred name
Ludwig, Bernd
Official Name
Ludwig, Bernd
Alternative Name
Ludwig, B.
Main Affiliation
Now showing 1 - 2 of 2
2015-09-27Journal Article [["dc.bibliographiccitation.firstpage","398"],["dc.bibliographiccitation.issue","3"],["dc.bibliographiccitation.journal","Kant-Studien"],["dc.bibliographiccitation.lastpage","417"],["dc.bibliographiccitation.volume","106"],["dc.contributor.affiliation","Ludwig, Bernd;"],["dc.contributor.author","Ludwig, Bernd"],["dc.date.accessioned","2022-11-28T10:23:00Z"],["dc.date.available","2022-11-28T10:23:00Z"],["dc.date.issued","2015-09-27"],["dc.date.updated","2022-11-27T10:12:53Z"],["dc.description.abstract","A famous passage in the first Critique (A 557 f.) often gives rise to the belief that Kant had not yet delivered a full treatment of freedom in 1781 and intended to shift this treatment to future writings. However, a closer inspection of the passage reveals that, to the contrary, Kant claims that due to the limitations of human reason his critical account of freedom given thus far must be considered complete. And indeed, this account reappears unchanged in the Groundwork. When considered in this light, not only do the exact achievements of the first Critique concerning Kant’s doctrine of freedom become evident, but so too does the further development of this doctrine. In 1785, the Groundwork supplies a new conceptual link between freedom and the moral law (and with it an explanation of the possibility of categorical imperatives). And thanks to this very link, Kant is able, in the second Critique (1787/88), to remedy a ‘dogmatic’ mistake (discovered by a reviewer in 1786) in his 1781/85 account of freedom."],["dc.identifier.doi","10.1515/kant-2015-0038"],["dc.identifier.gro","3145462"],["dc.identifier.uri","https://resolver.sub.uni-goettingen.de/purl?gro-2/117415"],["dc.language.iso","de"],["dc.notes.intern","aufklärung"],["dc.notes.status","final"],["dc.notes.submitter","oschaef1"],["dc.publisher","De Gruyter"],["dc.relation.eissn","1613-1134"],["dc.relation.issn","0022-8877"],["dc.title","‚Die Kritik der reinen Vernunft hat die Wirklichkeit der Freiheit nicht bewiesen, ja nicht einmal deren Möglichkeit.‘"],["dc.title.subtitle","Über die folgenreiche Fehlinterpretation eines Absatzes in der Kritik der reinen Vernunft."],["dc.type","journal_article"],["dc.type.internalPublication","yes"],["dc.type.peerReviewed","no"],["dspace.entity.type","Publication"]]Details DOI2018-03-21Journal Article [["dc.bibliographiccitation.firstpage","47"],["dc.bibliographiccitation.issue","1"],["dc.bibliographiccitation.journal","Kant-Studien"],["dc.bibliographiccitation.lastpage","71"],["dc.bibliographiccitation.volume","109"],["dc.contributor.affiliation","Bernd, Ludwig;"],["dc.contributor.author","Bernd, Ludwig"],["dc.date.accessioned","2022-11-28T10:22:24Z"],["dc.date.available","2022-11-28T10:22:24Z"],["dc.date.issued","2018-03-21"],["dc.date.updated","2022-11-27T10:12:49Z"],["dc.description.abstract","Abstract:Since H. J. Paton’s famous commentary from 1947, Kant’s interpreters have considered a ‘deduction of the categorical imperative’ a challenge. This is quite puzzling since Kant himself never talks about such a deduction - and the famous ‘deduction’ he does mention in Groundwork III.4 is, as a close reading shows, not at all the deduction of a law but the deduction of a concept, of the idea of a pure lawgiving will: Only the reality of this idea can explain the possibility of - prima facie impossible - categorical imperatives and thus of morality as autonomy. The presupposition of the validity of the moral law, however, was already a cornerstone of Kant’s critical metaphysics in 1781: Moral theology (which replaces all speculative proofs of immortality and of God’s existence) depends on the moral law’s being an undisputed datum without any need for philosophical justification (‘deduction’). While in the Groundwork (1785) Kant tried to show the practical reality of the idea of a pure will with the help of a speculative deduction of freedom (which a reviewer described as being ‘uncritical’ in May 1786), in the second Critique (1787/88) the reality of that very idea, and with it the idea of freedom, depends (as did immortality and God’s existence in 1781) on the aforementioned practical datum, which, from that point on, Kant called a “Factum der reinen Vernunft” [fact of pure reason]."],["dc.identifier.doi","10.1515/kant-2018-0001"],["dc.identifier.eissn","1613-1134"],["dc.identifier.issn","0022-8877"],["dc.identifier.uri","https://resolver.sub.uni-goettingen.de/purl?gro-2/117409"],["dc.language.iso","en"],["dc.notes.intern","DOI Import GROB-354"],["dc.publisher","De Gruyter"],["dc.relation.eissn","1613-1134"],["dc.relation.issn","0022-8877"],["dc.title","Über drei Deduktionen in Kants Moralphilosophie - und über eine vierte, die man dort vergeblich sucht. Zur Rehabilitierung von Grundlegung III"],["dc.type","journal_article"],["dc.type.internalPublication","yes"],["dspace.entity.type","Publication"]]Details DOI
2 results